Rational Decision Making in Business Organizations

Table of contents
- I. Decision Theory as Economic Science
- II. Challenging Marginalism and Exploring Alternatives
- III. The Rise of Normative Decision Theory and Computational Constraints
- IV. Characterizing Bounded Rationality and the Neoclassical Revival
- V. Advances in Behavioral Theory and Concluding Thoughts
- Reference Paper Link:

The article explores the shift from classical economics' assumption of perfect rationality to Herbert Simon's concept of bounded rationality, which acknowledges human cognitive limitations and influences decision-making processes. It highlights the implications of bounded rationality for decision theory, emphasizing the importance of understanding decision-making within real business organizations rather than relying solely on external market forces. The discussion also examines the challenges to classical theory, the rise of normative decision theory, and the impact of the behavioral theory of the firm on political economy. Emphasizing that decision-making processes matter, the article calls for robust sensitivity analyses in economic modeling and policy formulation.
For decades, classical economics operated under the powerful, yet often unrealistic, assumption of "perfect rationality." This concept portrayed economic actors – whether individuals or firms – as having complete information, unlimited computational abilities, and a crystal-clear understanding of their preferences. They were presumed to flawlessly maximize utility or profit, always selecting the optimal choice from a known set of alternatives. But what happens when we peel back the curtain and look at how decisions are actually made in the messy, complex, and uncertain world of real business organizations? That's precisely the question that Nobel Laureate Herbert A. Simon tackled in his groundbreaking work, and his insights have revolutionized our understanding of economics and decision theory.
Simon's research, powerfully articulated in his 1978 Nobel lecture, challenged the very foundations of neoclassical economics. Instead of "perfect rationality," he introduced the concept of "bounded rationality." This framework acknowledges the inherent limitations of human cognition. We simply don't have the mental capacity to process all available information, consider every possible outcome, and perform the intricate calculations required for true optimization. Instead, we rely on heuristics – mental shortcuts and rules of thumb – to simplify complex problems. We search for satisfactory solutions, not necessarily optimal ones, a process Simon termed "satisficing." This means we set aspiration levels and stop searching once we find an alternative that meets those criteria, even if a better option might exist somewhere further down the line.
This shift in perspective has profound implications. It moves us away from a world where decisions are determined solely by the external environment and into a realm where the internal, cognitive processes of the decision-maker become paramount. Simon's work draws heavily on psychology and organizational theory, examining how individuals and groups within organizations identify subgoals, manage information flow, and cope with uncertainty. His research delved into real-world business practices, using "anthropological" field studies to observe decision-making in action. These observations revealed that, instead of equating marginal costs and revenues, businesses often struggled with ill-defined production functions and conflicting internal perspectives. This led to a focus on understanding the process of decision-making, rather than simply assuming a predetermined outcome.
Simon's exploration extended beyond mere description. He, along with colleagues, explored the formal implications of bounded rationality, analyzing the employment relationship (why do we have organizations instead of just individual contracts?), organizational equilibrium (how do organizations maintain themselves through a balance of inducements and contributions?), and the mechanisms of search and satisficing. These theoretical investigations demonstrated that alternative models, based on realistic cognitive limitations, could provide equally robust, and in some cases superior, explanations for observed economic phenomena. Furthermore, and perhaps most importantly for the field of economics at large, Simon's work showed that assumptions of perfect rationality, often used as simplifications, were not just unrealistic, but actively led to flawed conclusions about aggregate economic behavior. This is the key takeaway: the process by which decisions are made matters, and ignoring the cognitive limitations of economic actors can lead to inaccurate predictions and misguided policy recommendations.
I. Decision Theory as Economic Science
At the heart of economics lies the study of how humans make choices, particularly in the context of allocating scarce resources. While Alfred Marshall, in his Principles, acknowledged the broad scope of economics as a study of mankind, the field has largely concentrated on the application of reason to allocation problems. This focus on rational decision-making, however, has created a vast landscape for economic inquiry, extending far beyond the traditional "Heartland" of political economy (focused on national and international economies, full employment, efficient allocation, and equitable distribution).
Within this broader empire of "economic sciences," the territory of decision theory holds a crucial, yet often underappreciated, position. Decision theory, in its broadest sense, encompasses both normative aspects (how decisions should be made) and descriptive aspects (how decisions are made). Its application to the theory of the firm serves as a critical bridge back to the core concerns of political economy. While a significant body of positive economic theory exists (for example, Walrasian general equilibrium and the work demonstrating the equivalence of competitive equilibrium and Pareto optimality), the relevance of some of this work to the real world has been a subject of ongoing debate.
A common, yet flawed, perspective argues that fundamental research in decision theory is only valuable if it directly contributes to the policy goals of political economy. This view discounts the intrinsic value of understanding human behavior in organizational settings. Just as in the natural sciences, where "idle" curiosity has often led to profound practical discoveries, understanding the fundamental processes of decision-making within firms holds immense potential, even if its immediate policy implications are not obvious. Another error in the economic sciences at large is to apply Occam's razor to a theory based on the brevity of its statement, rather than its actual underlying assumptions.
Further, the argument that micro-level decision-making theories are untestable, except through their aggregate predictions, is simply incorrect. We possess the tools – "microscopes," in Simon's analogy – to directly observe the decision-making processes within organizations. These observations, ranging from detailed case studies to real-time tracking of decision-making behavior, provide a rich source of data that goes far beyond aggregate time-series or financial statements. This data can, and should, be used to rigorously test and refine our theories of economic decision-making.
The importance is that the behavioral theory of the firm is important to construct the political economy, or better understand it. Even if this were not the case, studying how human behavior and rational thinking happen in business organizations is highly interesting to the scientific fields, and can lead to other practical applications.
II. Challenging Marginalism and Exploring Alternatives
The classical theory of the firm, with its reliance on perfect rationality and profit maximization, makes specific predictions about how businesses operate. A key tenet is that firms will adjust their inputs and outputs until marginal costs equal marginal revenues. This is the cornerstone of the marginalist approach. However, when we move from the theoretical elegance of this model to the empirical realities of business decision-making, a significant gap emerges.
Simon points out a crucial distinction: while economists often focus on aggregate predictions (like the negative slope of demand curves), the behavioral theory challenges the underlying mechanisms that supposedly generate these outcomes. It's not enough to say that the classical theory "works" because it predicts certain aggregate trends. We need to examine whether the assumed processes – the equating of marginals – actually occur. Simon and others argue that direct evidence of this is scarce.
Instead, many seemingly supportive findings for marginalism can be explained equally well, or even better, by theories of bounded rationality. For example, the negative slope of demand curves, a staple of introductory economics, doesn't necessarily imply utility maximization by consumers. As Gary Becker (a proponent of rational choice in other contexts) acknowledged, this phenomenon can arise from a wide range of decision rules, including those that fall far short of perfect optimization. Changes in relative prices alter the opportunity set, and even "irrational" actors will tend to respond systematically to these changes.
Similarly, the observation that fitted Cobb-Douglas production functions are often approximately homogeneous of degree one (meaning that doubling all inputs roughly doubles output) doesn't provide strong support for the classical theory. This result can be generated by simply fitting the function to data that fundamentally reflects a linear accounting identity (value of goods equals labor cost plus capital cost). The data, in this case, don't discriminate between the classical model and a simpler, less demanding behavioral explanation.
The long-run U-shaped cost curve, another prediction of classical theory (necessary for stable competitive equilibrium), also faces empirical challenges. Evidence from many industries suggests that long-run costs are often constant or even declining, a finding more consistent with stochastic models of firm growth than with static equilibrium models. Even observations like the correlation between executive salaries and the logarithm of company size, while explainable by classical theory, require ad hoc assumptions about the distribution of managerial ability. A simpler behavioral model, based on a culturally determined ratio between managerial and subordinate salaries, provides a more parsimonious explanation.
Many of the aggregate phenomena traditionally used to support classical theory fail to distinguish it from alternative models based on bounded rationality. In some cases, the behavioral models actually provide a better fit to the observed data. The classical theory begins to falter particularly when confronted with situations involving uncertainty and imperfect competition – areas where the "outguessing" of other actors becomes crucial. Statistical decision theory and game theory, while providing valuable conceptual tools, haven't resolved these issues. They often increase the computational burden on the decision-maker, and game theory, in particular, has highlighted the inherent difficulty of defining a universally accepted notion of rationality in strategic interactions.
III. The Rise of Normative Decision Theory and Computational Constraints
While the descriptive challenges to classical theory were mounting, another significant development occurred within the economic sciences: the growth of normative decision theory, often under the banners of "operations research" and "management science." This field, largely populated by individuals outside of traditional economics departments, focused on developing practical tools for making decisions, not just describing them. This practical imperative had a profound impact on the types of models that were developed.
The idealized models of optimizing entrepreneurs, with perfect information or complete probability distributions, were simply unusable in real-world contexts. The computational demands were overwhelming. Instead, management scientists had to develop models that were computationally tractable, even if it meant sacrificing some degree of theoretical elegance. This led to two main approaches:
Simplified Optimization: Retain the goal of optimization, but simplify the problem sufficiently to make it solvable. A classic example, discussed by Simon, is the use of quadratic cost functions in inventory management. This assumption, while unrealistic, leads to linear decision rules that are easily computed and provide "good enough" solutions, even in the face of uncertainty.
Satisficing Models: Abandon the goal of optimization altogether and instead search for solutions that are satisfactory, meeting predefined aspiration levels. This approach allows for a richer representation of the real world, incorporating factors that are difficult to quantify or optimize.
These two approaches highlight a fundamental trade-off: decision-makers can either find optimal solutions to simplified problems or satisfactory solutions to more realistic problems. Both approaches have coexisted and contributed to the development of management science. The key insight is that normative decision theory, like descriptive decision theory, is fundamentally concerned with the procedure of decision-making. It's about how to decide, not just what to decide. The development of new computational tools and more powerful computers continuously reshapes the landscape of normative decision theory, influencing both the recommendations it provides and the actual practices of businesses. This, in turn, can have significant macroeconomic consequences, as seen in the widespread adoption of formal inventory management techniques, which have demonstrably reduced average inventory holdings.
IV. Characterizing Bounded Rationality and the Neoclassical Revival
The initial formulation of bounded rationality, presented in Simon's Administrative Behavior, was, in a sense, a starting point – a recognition that human decision-making deviated significantly from the idealized assumptions of perfect rationality. It lacked, however, a fully developed positive theory of how these boundedly rational decisions were made. Subsequent research, both theoretical and empirical, aimed to fill this gap.
One stream of research focused on formalizing the key concepts of bounded rationality: search and satisficing. If alternatives are not readily apparent, decision-makers must engage in a search process. This search is not exhaustive; it's guided by heuristics and terminates when a satisfactory alternative is found. This "satisficing" behavior, rooted in psychological theories of aspiration levels, provides a mechanism for making decisions with limited information and computational resources.
Another critical area of inquiry was the exploration of the employment relationship. Why do we have firms with hierarchical authority structures, rather than relying solely on individual contracts? Simon's analysis, drawing parallels to Marschak's work on liquidity preference, highlighted the role of uncertainty. The employment contract allows employers to postpone specific task assignments until uncertainty is resolved, providing flexibility that benefits both parties.
Empirical studies, primarily "anthropological" field studies of organizational decision-making, provided further support for the bounded rationality framework. These studies, although often challenging to conduct and analyze, revealed the prevalence of subgoal identification, the influence of organizational context and individual experience on problem perception, and the use of simplifying heuristics. Work by Cyert and March, in their Behavioral Theory of the Firm, further developed these insights, providing a detailed account of how firms make decisions in practice.
Despite this progress, a "neoclassical revival" occurred in economics. Several factors contributed to this. First, methodological arguments defended classical theory, claiming that the realism of assumptions was irrelevant as long as the theory made accurate aggregate predictions (a position Simon strongly refutes). Second, the increasing mathematical sophistication of economics allowed for the development of more complex models within the neoclassical framework. These models, often incorporating elements of statistical decision theory and game theory, attempted to address issues of uncertainty and imperfect information while retaining the core assumption of optimization.
One prominent example is the "rational expectations" theory. This approach, initially inspired by the use of certainty equivalents in dynamic programming with quadratic cost functions (a simplification technique!), essentially assumes that economic agents' expectations are aligned with the predictions of the relevant economic theory. While elegant, this approach has faced theoretical challenges, particularly in dynamic environments where learning and structural changes occur. It also implicitly reintroduces the need for a theory of how expectations are formed, bringing back the very behavioral considerations it sought to avoid.
V. Advances in Behavioral Theory and Concluding Thoughts
Despite the neoclassical resurgence, behavioral theories of decision-making have continued to evolve. Research in psychology, particularly in the field of information processing psychology, has provided detailed insights into the micro-processes of human problem-solving. This work, often using computer simulations, highlights the role of selective search, heuristics, and satisficing in navigating complex problem spaces.
Organizational studies, although often in the form of case studies, continue to provide valuable evidence of how decisions are made in real-world business settings. These studies, while lacking the neatness of formal models, reveal the pervasive influence of bounded rationality.
A number of behavioral theories of the firm have emerged, each departing from classical assumptions in different ways. These include models incorporating satisficing goals, organizational slack, learning, and evolutionary dynamics. While diverse, these theories share a common thread: they recognize that the process of decision-making matters, and that firm behavior is not solely determined by external market forces.
This sensitivity of outcomes to process has crucial implications for political economy. Before drawing policy conclusions, we must perform sensitivity analyses, testing how robust our predictions are to different assumptions about decision-making at the micro level. If our conclusions are highly sensitive, we must proceed with caution, recognizing the limitations of models based on unrealistic assumptions.
Reference Paper Link:
Rational decision making in business organizations
Simon, H. A. (1979). Rational decision making in business organizations. The American economic review, 69(4), 493-513.
Subscribe to my newsletter
Read articles from Chubby Tummy directly inside your inbox. Subscribe to the newsletter, and don't miss out.
Written by
